doronshadmi
Penultimate Amazing
- Joined
- Mar 15, 2008
- Messages
- 13,320
By using a proof by contradiction Cantor proved that Power(X) > X.
Let us carefully examine this proof.
A question:
If –as a part of our proof– we define E and F in such a way that E > F, can we still claim that our proof holds?
Some facts:
1) A set is a collection of distinct objects (each object is included once and only once in a given set).
2) X is a set, and so is Power(X)
3) Let set D be the result of the mapping between Power(X) and X according to this rule:
The members of D are any X member that when mapped with some Power(X) member, this X member is not one of members this Power(X) member, for example:
In this particular example (out of infinitely many examples) D = {a, c, …}
There are two extreme versions of D which are:
D={} or D={a, b, c, d, …} , where each one of them is the result of infinitely many different mappings between Power(X) and X, but the general thing is this:
D={} only if each X member that is mapped with some arbitrary Power(X) member, is also a member of this arbitrary Power(X) member.
D={a, b, c, d, …} only if each X member that is mapped with some arbitrary Power(X) member, is not a member of this arbitrary Power(X) member.
Between D={} and D={a, b, c, d, …} we can define the infinitely many D results which are not D={} or D={a, b, c, d, …}.
So Cantor's method actually defines Power(X)={{}, … , {a, b, c, d, …}} as a part of a proof that says something about Power(X) (and in this case: Power(X) > X).
Furthermore, the result of how Power(X) is constructed by Cantor, cannot be but
Power(X) > X, because given any D (which is a Power(X) member) there is no X member that is mapped with D.
Some conclusions and questions:
1) We do not need a proof by contradiction in order to conclude that Power(X) > X,
because Cantor actually defines Power(X) (by D's) in such a way that the result cannot be but
Power(X) > X.
2) Is a proof is still a proof if we actually determine the result, as a pert of the proof?
3) Do we need the ZF axiom of the power set (after all Cantor's method actually defines it, without any need of this axiom)?
Let us carefully examine this proof.
A question:
If –as a part of our proof– we define E and F in such a way that E > F, can we still claim that our proof holds?
Some facts:
1) A set is a collection of distinct objects (each object is included once and only once in a given set).
2) X is a set, and so is Power(X)
3) Let set D be the result of the mapping between Power(X) and X according to this rule:
The members of D are any X member that when mapped with some Power(X) member, this X member is not one of members this Power(X) member, for example:
Code:
X Power(X)
a <--> {c,d}
b <--> {a,b}
c <--> {a,b,d,e,f,g,…}
d <--> {d,@,*}
…
There are two extreme versions of D which are:
D={} or D={a, b, c, d, …} , where each one of them is the result of infinitely many different mappings between Power(X) and X, but the general thing is this:
D={} only if each X member that is mapped with some arbitrary Power(X) member, is also a member of this arbitrary Power(X) member.
D={a, b, c, d, …} only if each X member that is mapped with some arbitrary Power(X) member, is not a member of this arbitrary Power(X) member.
Between D={} and D={a, b, c, d, …} we can define the infinitely many D results which are not D={} or D={a, b, c, d, …}.
So Cantor's method actually defines Power(X)={{}, … , {a, b, c, d, …}} as a part of a proof that says something about Power(X) (and in this case: Power(X) > X).
Furthermore, the result of how Power(X) is constructed by Cantor, cannot be but
Power(X) > X, because given any D (which is a Power(X) member) there is no X member that is mapped with D.
Some conclusions and questions:
1) We do not need a proof by contradiction in order to conclude that Power(X) > X,
because Cantor actually defines Power(X) (by D's) in such a way that the result cannot be but
Power(X) > X.
2) Is a proof is still a proof if we actually determine the result, as a pert of the proof?
3) Do we need the ZF axiom of the power set (after all Cantor's method actually defines it, without any need of this axiom)?
Last edited: